If nature transmitted information in both directions within
organisms, it would allow the possibility of Lamarckian evolution, which
requires two-way communication between gene and its products. The
advantages of Lamarckism are awesome. When an animal needs faster legs
to survive, it could use body-to-gene communication to direct the genes
to make faster leg muscles, and then pass that innovation on to its
offspring. Evolution would accelerate madly.
But Lamarckian evolution requires an organism to have a working index to
its genes. If the organism met a harsh environment -- say extreme high
altitude -- it would notify all the genes in its body able to influence
respiration and ask them to adjust. The body of an organism can
certainly communicate that message to other organs in the body by
hardwired hormone and chemical circuits. And it could communicate the
same to the genes if it could pinpoint the right ones. But that is the
bookkeeping chore that is missing. The body does not keep track of how
it solves a problem, so it cannot pinpoint which genes to pump up the
muscle on the blacksmith's biceps, or which genes regulate respiration
and blood pressure. And because there are millions of genes producing
billions of features -- and one gene can make more than one feature and one
feature can be made by more than one gene -- the complexity of accounting
and indexing could exceed the complexity of the organism itself.
So it isn't so much that information can't be transmitted in the body to
gene direction, it's more that communication is blocked because messages
have no distinct destination. There is no central gene-authority to
direct traffic. The genome is the ultimate decentralized system -- rampant
redundancy, massive parallelism, no one in charge, no one looking over
the shoulder of every transaction.
But what if there is some way around this? Genuine two-way genetic
communication would light up an interesting bunch of questions: Would
there be any biological advantage if such a mechanism were possible?
What else would it take to have a Lamarckian biology? Could there have
been a biological route to such a mechanism at one time? If it is
possible, why hasn't it happened? Could we outline a working biological
Lamarckism as a thought experiment?
In all probability, Lamarckian biology requires a type of deep
complexity -- an intelligence -- that most organisms can't reach. But where
complexity is rich enough for intelligence, such as in human organisms
and organizations, and their robotic offspring, Lamarckian evolution is
possible and advantageous. Ackley and Littman showed that computers
programmed by humans could run Lamarckian evolution.
But in the last decade, mainstream biologists have acknowledged an
observation a few maverick biologists have preached for a century: that
when an organism acquires sufficient complexity in its body, it can use
its body to teach the genes what they need to know to evolve. Because
this mechanism is a hybrid of evolution and learning, it has great
potential in artificial realms.
Every animal's body has a built-in but limited power to adjust to
different environments. Humans can acclimatize to life at a
significantly higher elevation. Our heart rate, blood pressure, and lung
capacity must and will compensate for the lower air pressure. The same
changes reverse when we migrate to a lower elevation. But there is a
limit to the degree to which we can acclimatize. For us, it's around
20,000 feet above sea level. Beyond this altitude, the human body cannot
stretch itself for long-term habitation.
Imagine a settlement of people living high in the Andes. They have moved
from the plains into a niche where they are not exactly best suited -- the
air is thin. For the thousands of years they have lived there, their
hearts and lungs -- their bodies -- have had to work overtime to keep up with
the altitude. If a "freak" should be born in their village, one whose
body has a genetically more proficient way to handle the stress of high
altitudes -- say, a better hemoglobin variety rather than faster
heartbeat -- then the freak has an advantage. If the freak has children,
then this trait could potentially spread through the village over
generations because it is an advantage to lower stress on the heart and
lungs. By the usual Darwinian dynamics of natural selection, the
mutation of altitude acclimation comes to dominate the village gene
pool.
On the surface there appears to be nothing but classical Darwinism at
work here. But in order for Darwinian evolution to take place, the
organism first had to survive in the niche for many generations without
the benefit of genetic change. Thus it was the flexibility of the body
that kept the population surviving long enough for the mutation to arise
and fix itself in the gene. An adaptation spearheaded by the body (a
somatic adaptation) is assimilated over time by the genes. Theoretical
biologist C. H. Waddington called this transfer "genetic assimilation."
Cyberneticist Gregory Bateson called it "somatic adaptation." Bateson
likened it to legislative change in society -- first a change is made by
the people, then it is made law. Writes Bateson, "The wise legislator
will only rarely initiate a new rule of behavior; more usually he will
confine himself to affirming in law that which has already become the
custom of the people." In the technical literature, this genetic
affirmation is also known as the Baldwin effect, after J. M. Baldwin, a
psychologist who first published the idea as a "New Factor in Evolution"
in 1896.
Let's say there is this other village in the mountains, this time in the
Himalayas, in a valley called Shangri La, whose residents' bodies are
able to acclimatize up to 30,000 feet -- 10,000 more than the Andes
folks -- but who are also able to live at sea level. Over generations a
mutation spreads to hardwire this talent into the villagers' genes, just
as it did in the Andes. Of the two alpine villages, the Himalayan
population now has a body type that is more stretchable, more flexible,
and therefore, in essence, more evolutionarily adaptable. It may seem
like a textbook example of Lamarckism, but giraffes who can evolve the
most stretch in their necks can stake out an adaptation with their
bodies long enough for their genes to catch up. As long as they keep
their hides adjustable to a wide range of stresses, they'll have a
competitive advantage in the long run.
The evolutionary moral is that it pays to invest in a flexible
phenotype. It makes better sense to keep an adaptable body in service
than to have a rigid body wait around for a mutation to pop up anytime
an adaptation is needed. But somatic flexibility is "expensive." An
organism cannot be equally flexible everywhere, and accommodating one
stress will decrease its ability to accommodate another. Hardwiring is
more efficient, but it takes time; for hardwiring to work, the stress
must remain constant over a long period. In a rapidly changing
environment, the tradeoff favors keeping the body flexible. An agile
body can foreshadow, or more accurately, try out possible genetic
adaptations, and then hold a steady line to them, as a hunting dog holds
to a grouse.
But the story is even more radical than it appears because it is
behavior that moves the body. The giraffe had to first want (for
whatever giraffey reasons) higher leaves, and then had to reach for them
over and over again. The humans had to choose to move to more alpine
villages. By behavior, an organism can scout its options, and explore
its space of possible adaptations.
Waddington said genetic assimilation, or the Baldwin effect, was about
converting acquired traits into inherited traits. What it really comes
down to is the natural selection of traits controls. Genetic
assimilation bumps up the reach of evolution a notch. Instead of being
able to tune the dial to the best trait, somatic and behavioral
adaptation gives evolution quicker control over what the dials are and
how far and in what direction they turn.
Behavioral adaptation works in other ways, too. Naturalists have
verified that animals are constantly roaming out of their adapted
environment and taking up homes in areas where they "don't belong."
Coyotes creep too far south, or mockingbirds migrate too far north. And
then, they stay. Their genes endorse the change by assimilating an
adaptation which began, perhaps, as a vague desire.
What begins as vague desire can skate dangerously close to the edge of
classical Lamarckism when it reaches individual learning. One species of
finch learned to pick up a cactus needle to poke for insects. By this
behavior the finch opened up a new niche to itself. By
learning -- perceived as a deliberate act -- it altered its evolution. It is
entirely possible, if not probable, that its learning will affect its
genes.
Some computerists use the term "learning" in a loose, cybernetic sense.
Gregory Bateson described the flexibility of the body as a type of
learning. He saw little in its effect to distinguish the kind of search
the body performed from the kind of search that either evolution or mind
did. By this reckoning, a flexible body learns to acclimatize to
stresses. "Learn" means adaptation within a lifetime instead of over
lifetimes. The computerists make no real distinction between behavioral
learning and somatic learning. What matters is that both types of
adaptation search the fitness space within the lifetime of an
individual.
An organism has great room to reshape itself within its lifetime. Robert
Reid, at the University of Victoria, Canada, suggests that organisms can
respond to environmental change with the following types of
plasticity: -
Morphological plasticity
(An organism can have more than one body form.) -
Physiological adaptability
(An organism's tissues can modify themselves to accommodate stress.)
-
Behavioral flexibility
(An organism can do something new or move.) -
Intelligent choice
(An organism can choose, or not, based on past experiences.) -
Guidance from tradition
(An organism can be influenced or taught by others' experiences.)
Each of these freedoms is a front along which the organism can search
for better ways to refit itself in a coevolutionary environment. In the
sense that they are adaptations within a lifetime which can later be
assimilated, we can call these five options, five varieties of
inheritable learning.
continue...
|