In 1916, Frederic Clements, one of the founding fathers of
ecology, called a community of creatures such as the beech hardwood
forest an emergent superorganism. In his words, a climax formation is a
superorganism because it "arises, grows, matures, and
dies....comparable in its chief features with the life history of an
individual plant." Since a forest could reseed itself on an abandoned
Michigan field, Clements portrayed that act as reproduction, a further
characteristic of an organism. To any astute observer, a beech-maple
forest displays an integrity and identity as much as a crow does. What
else but a (super)organism could reproduce itself so reliably,
propagating on empty fields and sandy barrens?
Superorganism was a buzz word among biologists in the 1920s. They used
it to describe the then novel idea that a collection of agents could act
in concert to produce phenomena governed by the collective. Like a slime
mold that assembled itself from moldy spots into a thrusting blob, an
ecosystem coalesced into a stable superorganization -- a hive or forest. A
Georgia pine forest did not act like a pine tree, nor a Texas sagebrush
desert like a sagebrush, just as a flock is not a big bird. They were
something else, a loose federation of animals and plants united into an
emergent superorganism exhibiting distinctive behavior.
A rival of Clements, biologist H. A. Gleason, the other father of modern
ecology, thought the superorganism federation was too flabby and too
much the product of a human mind looking for patterns. In opposition to
Clements, Gleason proposed that the climax community was merely a
fortuitous association of organisms that came and went depending on
climate and geological conditions. An ecosystem was more like a
conference than a community -- indefinite, pluralistic, tolerant, and in
constant flux.
The wilds of nature hold evidence for both views. In places the boundary
between communities is decisive, much as one expects if ecosystems are
superorganisms. Along the rocky coast of the Pacific Northwest, for
instance, the demarcation between the high tide seaweed community and
the watery edge of the spruce forest is an extreme no-man's-land of
barren beach. One can stand on this yard-wide strip of salty desert and
sense the two superorganisms on either side, fidgeting in their separate
lives. As another example, the border between deciduous forest and
wildflower prairie in the midwest is remarkably impermeable.
In search of an answer to the riddle of ecological superorganisms,
biologist William Hamilton began modeling ecosystems on computers in the
1970s. He found that in his models (as well as in real life) very few
systems were able to self-organize into any kind of lasting coherence.
My examples above are a few exceptions in the wild. He found a few
others: a sphagnum moss peat bog can repel the invasion of pine trees
for thousands of years. Ditto for the tundra steppes. But most
ecological communities stumble along into a mongrel mixture of species
that offers no outstanding self-protection to the group as a team. Most
ecological communities, both simulated and real, can be easily invaded
in the longer run.
Gleason was right. The couplings between members of an ecosystem are far
more flexible and transient than the couplings between members of an
organism. The cybernetic difference between an organism such as a
pollywog and an ecosystem such as a fresh-water bog is that an organism
is tightly bound, and strict; an ecosystem is loosely bound, and lax.
In the long view, ecologies are temporary networks. Although some links
become hardwired and nearly symbiotic, most species are promiscuous in
evolutionary time, shacking up with a different partners as the partners
themselves evolve.
In this light of evolutionary time, ecology can be seen as one long
dress rehearsal. It's an identity workshop for biological forms. Species
try out different roles with one another and explore partnerships. Over
time, roles and performance are assimilated by an organism's genes. In
poetic language, the gene is reluctant to assimilate into its code any
interactions and functions directly based upon its neighbors' ways
because the neighborhood can shift at any evolutionary moment. It pays
to stay flexible, unattached, and uncommitted.
At the same time Clements was right. There is a basin of efficiency
that, all things being equal, will draw down a certain mix of parts into
a stable harmony. As a metaphor, consider the way rocks make their way
to the valley floor. Not all rocks will land at the bottom; a particular
rock may get stuck on a small hill somewhere. In the same way, stable
intermediate less-than-climax mixtures of species can be found in
places on the landscape. For extremely short periods of geological
time -- hundreds of thousands of years -- ecosystems form an intimate troupe
of players, who brook no interference and need no extras. These
associations are far briefer than even the brief life of individual
species, which typically flame-out after a million years or two.
Evolution requires a certain connectance among its participants to
express its power; and so evolutionary dynamics exert themselves most
forcefully in tightly coupled systems. In systems connected loosely,
such as ecosystems, economic systems, and cultural systems, a less
structured adaptation takes place. We know very little about the general
dynamics of loosely coupled systems because this kind of distributed
change is messy and infinitely indirect. Howard Pattee, an early
cybernetician, defined hierarchical structure as a spectrum of
connectance. He said, "To a Platonic mind, everything in the world is
connected to everything else -- and perhaps it is. Everything is connected,
but some things are more connected than others." Hierarchy for Pattee
was the product of differential connectedness within one system. Members
that were so loosely connected as to be "flat" would tend to form a
separate organizational level distinct from areas where members were
tightly connected. The range of connectance created a hierarchy.
In the most general terms, evolution is a tight web and ecology a loose
one. Evolutionary change seems a strongly bound process very similar to
mathematical computation, or even to thinking. In this way it is
"cerebral." Ecological change, on the other hand, seems a weak-minded,
circuitous process, centered in bodies shoved against wind, water,
gravity, sunlight, and rock. "Community [ecological] attributes are more
the product of environment than the product of evolutionary history,"
writes ecologist Robert Ricklefs. While evolution is governed by the
straightforward flow of symbolic information issuing from the gene or
computer chips, ecology is governed by the far less abstract, far more
untidy complexity embodied by flesh.
Because evolution is such a symbolic process, we now can artificially
create it and attempt to govern it. But because ecological change is so
body bound, we cannot synthesize it well until we can more easily
simulate bodies and richer artificial environments.
continue...
|